Below is a precis of an article about the materialist establishment's conniptions over perceived heretic Thomas Nagel. It is very well written and well worth perusing.
The Heretic
Who is Thomas Nagel and why are so many of his fellow academics condemning him?
Mar 25, 2013, Vol. 18, No. 27
• By ANDREW FERGUSON
Last fall, a few days before Halloween and about a month after the publication of Mind and Cosmos,
the controversial new book by the philosopher Thomas Nagel, several of
the world’s leading philosophers gathered with a group of cutting-edge
scientists in the conference room of a charming inn in the Berkshires.
They faced one another around a big table set with pitchers of iced
water and trays of hard candies wrapped in cellophane and talked and
talked, as public intellectuals do. PowerPoint was often brought into
play.
The
title of the “interdisciplinary workshop” was “Moving Naturalism
Forward.” For those of us who like to kill time sitting around pondering
the nature of reality—personhood, God, moral judgment, free will, what
have you—this was the Concert for Bangladesh.
The biologist Richard Dawkins was there, author of The Blind Watchmaker, The Selfish Gene, and other bestselling books of popular science, and so was Daniel Dennett, a philosopher at Tufts and author of Consciousness Explained and Darwin’s Dangerous Idea: Evolution and the Meanings of Life. So were the authors of Why Evolution is True, The Really Hard Problem: Meaning in a Material World, Everything Must Go: Metaphysics Naturalized, and The Atheist’s Guide to Reality: Enjoying Life without Illusions—all of them books that to one degree or another bring to a larger audience the world as scientists have discovered it to be.
The biologist Richard Dawkins was there, author of The Blind Watchmaker, The Selfish Gene, and other bestselling books of popular science, and so was Daniel Dennett, a philosopher at Tufts and author of Consciousness Explained and Darwin’s Dangerous Idea: Evolution and the Meanings of Life. So were the authors of Why Evolution is True, The Really Hard Problem: Meaning in a Material World, Everything Must Go: Metaphysics Naturalized, and The Atheist’s Guide to Reality: Enjoying Life without Illusions—all of them books that to one degree or another bring to a larger audience the world as scientists have discovered it to be.
Contemporary philosophers have a name for the way you and I
see the world, a world filled with other people, with colors and
sounds, sights and sensations, things that are good and things that are
bad and things that are very good indeed: ourselves, who are able, more
or less, to make our own way through life, by our own lights.
Philosophers call this common view the “manifest image.” Daniel Dennett
pointed out at the conference that modern science, at least since the
revelations of Darwin, has been piling up proof that the manifest image
is not really accurate in any scientific sense. Rather science—this vast
interlocking combine of genetics, neuroscience, evolutionary biology,
particle physics—tells us that the components of the manifest image are
illusory.
Color, for instance: That azalea outside the window may
look red to you, but in reality it has no color at all. The red comes
from certain properties of the azalea that absorb some kinds of light
and reflect other kinds of light, which are then received by the eye and
transformed in our brains into a subjective experience of red.
And
sounds, too: Complex vibrations in the air are soundless in reality, but
our ears are able to turn the vibrations into a car alarm or a cat’s
meow or, worse, the voice of Mariah Carey. These capacities of the human
organism are evolutionary adaptations. Everything about human beings,
by definition, is an evolutionary adaptation. Our sense that the colors
and sounds exist “out there” and not merely in our brain is a convenient
illusion that long ago increased the survival chances of our species.
Powered by Darwin, modern science proceeds, in Dennett’s phrase, as a
“universal corrosive,” destroying illusions all the way up and all the
way down, dismantling our feelings of freedom and separate selfhood, our
morals and beliefs, a mother’s love and a patient’s prayer: All in
reality are just “molecules in motion.”
The most famous, most succinct, and most pitiless summary
of the manifest image’s fraudulence was written nearly 20 years ago by
the geneticist Francis Crick: “ ‘You,’ your joys and your sorrows, your
memories and your ambitions, your sense of personal identity and free
will, are in fact no more than the behavior of a vast assembly of nerve
cells and their associated molecules. Who you are is nothing but a pack
of neurons.”
This view is the “naturalism” that the workshoppers in the
Berkshires were trying to move forward. Naturalism is also called
“materialism,” the view that only matter exists; or “reductionism,” the
view that all life, from tables to daydreams, is ultimately reducible to
pure physics; or “determinism,” the view that every phenomenon,
including our own actions, is determined by a preexisting cause, which
was itself determined by another cause, and so on back to the Big Bang.
The naturalistic project has been greatly aided by neo-Darwinism, the
application of Darwin’s theory of natural selection to human behavior,
including areas of life once assumed to be nonmaterial: emotions and
thoughts and habits and perceptions. . . .
Thomas Nagel may be the most famous philosopher in the
United States—a bit like being the best power forward in the Lullaby
League, but still. His paper “What Is It Like to Be a Bat?” was
recognized as a classic when it was published in 1974 . . . . Nagel occupies an endowed chair at NYU as a University
Professor, a rare and exalted position that frees him to teach whatever
course he wants. . . . For all this and more, Thomas Nagel is a prominent and
heretofore respected member of the country’s intellectual elite. And
such men are not supposed to write books with subtitles like the one he
tacked onto Mind and Cosmos: Why the Materialist Neo-Darwinian Conception of Nature Is Almost Certainly False.
The Guardian awarded Mind and Cosmos its
prize for the Most Despised Science Book of 2012. The reviews were
numerous and overwhelmingly negative; one of the kindest, in the British
magazine Prospect, carried the defensive headline “Thomas
Nagel is not crazy.” (Really, he’s not!) Most other reviewers weren’t so
sure about that. . . .
“Thomas Nagel is of absolutely no importance on this
subject,” wrote one. “He’s a self-contradictory idiot,” opined another.
Some made simple appeals to authority and left it at that: “Haven’t
these guys ever heard of Richard Dawkins and Daniel Dennett?” The hearts
of still others were broken at seeing a man of Nagel’s eminence sink so
low. “It is sad that Nagel, whom my friends and I thought back in the
1960’s could leap over tall buildings with a single bound, has tripped
over the Bible and fallen on his face. Very sad.” . . . .
“Evolutionists,” one reviewer huffily wrote, “will feel
they’ve been ravaged by a sheep.” Many reviewers attacked the book on
cultural as well as philosophical or scientific grounds, wondering aloud
how a distinguished house like Oxford University Press could allow such
a book to be published. The Philosophers’ Magazine described it with the curious word “irresponsible.” . . .
But what about fans of apostasy? You don’t have to be a biblical fundamentalist or a young-earth creationist or an intelligent design enthusiast—I’m none of the above, for what it’s worth—to find Mind and Cosmos exhilarating. “For a long time I have found the materialist account of how we and our fellow organisms came to exist hard to believe,” Nagel writes. “It is prima facie highly implausible that life as we know it is the result of a sequence of physical accidents together with the mechanism of natural selection.” The prima facie impression, reinforced by common sense, should carry more weight than the clerisy gives it. “I would like to defend the untutored reaction of incredulity to the reductionist neo-Darwinian account of the origin and evolution of life.”
The incredulity is not simply a matter of scientific
ignorance, as the materialists would have it. It arises from something
more fundamental and intimate. The neo-Darwinian materialist account
offers a picture of the world that is unrecognizable to us—a world
without color or sound, and also a world without free will or
consciousness or good and evil or selves or, when it comes to that,
selflessness. “It flies in the face of common sense,” he says.
Materialism is an explanation for a world we don’t live in.
Nagel’s tone is measured and tentative, but there’s no
disguising the book’s renegade quality. There are flashes of
exasperation and dismissive impatience. What’s exhilarating is that the
source of Nagel’s exasperation is, so to speak, his own tribe: the
“secular theoretical establishment and the contemporary enlightened
culture which it dominates.” The establishment today, he says, is
devoted beyond all reason to a “dominant scientific naturalism, heavily
dependent on Darwinian explanations of practically everything, and armed
to the teeth against attacks from religion.” . . .
Nagel follows the materialist chain of reasoning all the
way into the cul de sac where it inevitably winds up. Nagel’s touchier
critics have accused him of launching an assault on science, when really
it is an assault on the nonscientific uses to which materialism has
been put. . . . Materialism, then, is fine as far as it goes. It just
doesn’t go as far as materialists want it to. It is a premise of
science, not a finding. Scientists do their work by assuming that every
phenomenon can be reduced to a material, mechanistic cause and by
excluding any possibility of nonmaterial explanations. And the
materialist assumption works really, really well—in detecting and
quantifying things that have a material or mechanistic explanation.
Materialism has allowed us to predict and control what happens in nature
with astonishing success. The jaw-dropping edifice of modern science,
from space probes to nanosurgery, is the result.
But the success has gone to the materialists’ heads. From a
fruitful method, materialism becomes an axiom: If science can’t
quantify something, it doesn’t exist, and so the subjective,
unquantifiable, immaterial “manifest image” of our mental life is proved
to be an illusion.
Here materialism bumps up against itself. Nagel insists
that we know some things to exist even if materialism omits or ignores
or is oblivious to them. Reductive materialism doesn’t account for the
“brute facts” of existence—it doesn’t explain, for example, why the
world exists at all, or how life arose from non-life. Closer to home, it
doesn’t plausibly explain the fundamental beliefs we rely on as we go
about our everyday business: the truth of our subjective experience, our
ability to reason, our capacity to recognize that some acts are
virtuous and others aren’t. These failures, Nagel says, aren’t just
temporary gaps in our knowledge, waiting to be filled in by new
discoveries in science. On its own terms, materialism cannot
account for brute facts. Brute facts are irreducible, and materialism,
which operates by breaking things down to their physical components,
stands useless before them. “There is little or no possibility,” he
writes, “that these facts depend on nothing but the laws of physics.”
In a dazzling six-part tour de force rebutting Nagel’s
critics, the philosopher Edward Feser provided a good analogy to
describe the basic materialist error—the attempt to stretch materialism
from a working assumption into a comprehensive explanation of the world.
Feser suggests a parody of materialist reasoning: “1. Metal detectors
have had far greater success in finding coins and other metallic objects
in more places than any other method has. 2. Therefore we have good
reason to think that metal detectors can reveal to us everything that
can be revealed” about metallic objects.
But of course a metal detector only detects the metallic
content of an object; it tells us nothing about its color, size, weight,
or shape. In the same way, Feser writes, the methods of “mechanistic
science are as successful as they are in predicting and controlling
natural phenomena precisely because they focus on only those aspects of nature susceptible to prediction and control.”
Meanwhile, they ignore everything else. But this is a
fatal weakness for a theory that aspires to be a comprehensive picture
of the world. With magnetic resonance imaging, science can tell us which
parts of my brain light up when, for example, I glimpse my daughter’s
face in a crowd; the bouncing neurons can be observed and measured.
Science cannot quantify or describe the feelings I experience when I see
my daughter. Yet the feelings are no less real than the neurons.
The point sounds more sentimental than it is. My bouncing
neurons and my feelings of love and obligation are unquestionably bound
together. But the difference between the neurons and the feelings, the
material and the mental, is a qualitative difference, a difference in
kind. And of the two, reductive materialism can capture only one.
“The world is an astonishing place,” Nagel writes. “That
it has produced you, and me, and the rest of us is the most astonishing
thing about it.” Materialists are in the business of banishing
astonishment; they want to demystify the world and human beings along
with it, to show that everything we see as a mystery is reducible to
components that aren’t mysterious at all. And they cling to this
ambition even in cases where doing so is obviously fruitless.
Neo-Darwinism insists that every phenomenon, every species, every trait
of every species, is the consequence of random chance, as natural
selection requires. And yet, Nagel says, “certain things are so
remarkable that they have to be explained as non-accidental if we are to pretend to a real understanding of the world.” (The italics are mine.)
Among these remarkable, nonaccidental things are many of
the features of the manifest image. Consciousness itself, for example:
You can’t explain consciousness in evolutionary terms, Nagel says,
without undermining the explanation itself. Evolution easily accounts
for rudimentary kinds of awareness. Hundreds of thousands of years ago
on the African savannah, where the earliest humans evolved the unique
characteristics of our species, the ability to sense danger or to read
signals from a potential mate would clearly help an organism survive.
So far, so good. But the human brain can do much more than
this. It can perform calculus, hypothesize metaphysics, compose
music—even develop a theory of evolution. None of these higher
capacities has any evident survival value, certainly not hundreds of
thousands of years ago when the chief aim of mental life was to avoid
getting eaten. Could our brain have developed and sustained such
nonadaptive abilities by the trial and error of natural selection, as
neo-Darwinism insists? It’s possible, but the odds, Nagel says, are
“vanishingly small.” If Nagel is right, the materialist is in a pickle.
The conscious brain that is able to come up with neo-Darwinism as a
universal explanation simultaneously makes neo-Darwinism, as a universal
explanation, exceedingly unlikely.
A similar argument holds for our other cognitive
capacities. “The evolution story leaves the authority of reason in a
much weaker position,” he writes. Neo-Darwinism tells us that we have
the power of reason because reason was adaptive; it must have helped us
survive, back in the day. Yet reason often conflicts with our intuition
or our emotion—capacities that must also have been adaptive and
essential for survival. Why should we “privilege” one capacity over
another when reason and intuition conflict? On its own terms, the scheme
of neo-Darwinism gives us no standard by which we should choose one
adaptive capacity over the other. And yet neo-Darwinists insist we
embrace neo-Darwinism because it conforms to our reason, even though it
runs against our intuition. Their defense of reason is unreasonable.
So too our moral sense. We all of us have confidence, to
one degree or another, that “our moral judgments are objectively
valid”—that is, while our individual judgments might be right or wrong, what makes them right or wrong is real,
not simply fantasy or opinion. Two and two really do make four. Why is
this confidence inherent in our species? How was it adaptive?
Neo-Darwinian materialists tell us that morality evolved as a survival
mechanism (like everything else): We developed an instinct for behavior
that would help us survive, and we called this behavior good as a means
of reinforcing it. We did the reverse for behavior that would hurt our
chances for survival: We called it bad. Neither type of behavior was
good or bad in reality; such moral judgments are just useful tricks
human beings have learned to play on ourselves.
Yet Nagel points out that our moral sense, even at the
most basic level, developed a complexity far beyond anything needed for
survival, even on the savannah—even in Manhattan. We are, as Nagel
writes, “beings capable of thinking successfully about good and bad,
right and wrong, and discovering moral and evaluative truths that do not
depend on [our] own beliefs.” And we behave accordingly, or try to. The
odds that such a multilayered but nonadaptive capacity should become a
characteristic of the species through natural selection are, again,
implausibly long. . . .
In this sense too Nagel is a throwback, daring not only to
interpret science but to contradict scientists. He admits it’s
“strange” when he relies “on a philosophical claim to refute a
scientific theory supported by empirical evidence.” But he knows that
when it comes to cosmology, scientists are just as likely to make an
error of philosophy as philosophers are to make an error of science. And
Nagel is accused of making large errors indeed. According to Leiter and
Weisberg and the others, he is ignorant of how science is actually done
these days.
Nagel, say Leiter and Weisberg, overestimates the
importance of materialism, even as a scientific method. He’s attacking a
straw man. He writes as though “reductive materialism really were
driving the scientific community.” In truth, they say, most scientists
reject theoretical reductionism. Fifty years ago, many philosophers and
scientists might have believed that all the sciences were ultimately
reducible to physics, but modern science doesn’t work that way.
Psychologists, for example, aren’t trying to reduce psychology to
biology; and biologists don’t want to boil biology down to chemistry;
and chemists don’t want to reduce chemistry to physics. Indeed, an
evolutionary biologist—even one who’s a good materialist—won’t refer to
physics at all in the course of his work!
And this point is true, as Nagel himself writes in his
book: Theoretical materialism, he says, “is not a necessary condition of
the practice of any of those sciences.” Researchers can believe in
materialism or not, as they wish, and still make scientific progress.
(This is another reason why it’s unconvincing to cite scientific
progress as evidence for the truth of materialism.) But the critics’
point is also disingenuous. If materialism is true as an explanation of
everything—and they insist it is—then psychological facts, for example, must
be reducible to biology, and then down to chemistry, and finally down
to physics. If they weren’t reducible in this way, they would (ta-da!)
be irreducible. And any fact that’s irreducible would, by definition, be
uncaused and undetermined; meaning it wouldn’t be material. It might
even be spooky stuff.
On this point Leiter and Weisberg were gently chided by
the prominent biologist Jerry Coyne, who was also a workshopper in the
Berkshires. He was delighted by their roasting of Nagel in the Nation,
but he accused them of going wobbly on materialism—of shying away from
the hard conclusions that reductive materialism demands. It’s not
surprising that scientists in various disciplines aren’t actively trying
to reduce all science to physics; that would be a theoretical problem
that is only solvable in the distant future. However: “The view that all
sciences are in principle reducible to the laws of physics,”
he wrote, “must be true unless you’re religious.” Either we’re molecules
in motion or we’re not.
You can sympathize with Leiter and Weisberg for fudging on
materialism. As a philosophy of everything it is an undeniable drag. As
a way of life it would be even worse. Fortunately, materialism is never
translated into life as it’s lived. As colleagues and friends, husbands
and mothers, wives and fathers, sons and daughters, materialists never
put their money where their mouth is. Nobody thinks his daughter is just
molecules in motion and nothing but; nobody thinks the Holocaust was
evil, but only in a relative, provisional sense. A materialist who lived
his life according to his professed convictions—understanding himself
to have no moral agency at all, seeing his friends and enemies and
family as genetically determined robots—wouldn’t just be a materialist:
He’d be a psychopath. Say what you will about Leiter and Weisberg and
the workshoppers in the Berkshires. From what I can tell, none of them
is a psychopath. Not even close.
Applied beyond its own usefulness as a scientific methodology, materialism is, as Nagel suggests, self-evidently absurd. Mind and Cosmos
can be read as an extended paraphrase of Orwell’s famous insult: “One
has to belong to the intelligentsia to believe things like that: no
ordinary man could be such a fool.” Materialism can only be taken
seriously as a philosophy through a heroic feat of cognitive dissonance;
pretending, in our abstract, intellectual life, that values like truth
and goodness have no objective content even as, in our private life, we
try to learn what’s really true and behave in a way we know to be good.
Nagel has sealed his ostracism from the intelligentsia by idly
speculating why his fellow intellectuals would undertake such a feat.
“The priority given to evolutionary naturalism in the face
of its implausible conclusions,” he writes, “is due, I think, to the
secular consensus that this is the only form of external understanding
of ourselves that provides an alternative to theism.”
In a recent review in the New York Review of Books of Where the Conflict Really Lies,
by the Christian philosopher Alvin Plantinga, Nagel told how
instinctively he recoils from theism, and how hungry he is for a
reasonable alternative. “If I ever found myself flooded with the
conviction that what the Nicene Creed says is true,” he wrote, “the most
likely explanation would be that I was losing my mind, not that I was
being granted the gift of faith.” He admits that he finds the evident
failure of materialism as a worldview alarming—precisely because the
alternative is, for a secular intellectual, unthinkable. He calls this
intellectual tic “fear of religion.”
“I speak from experience, being strongly subject to this
fear,” he wrote not long ago in an essay called “Evolutionary Naturalism
and the Fear of Religion.” “I want atheism to be true and am made
uneasy by the fact that some of the most intelligent and well-informed
people I know are religious believers. It isn’t just that I don’t
believe in God and, naturally, hope that I’m right in my belief. It’s
that I hope there is no God! I don’t want there to be a God; I don’t
want the universe to be like that.”
Nagel believes this “cosmic authority problem” is widely
shared among intellectuals, and I believe him. It accounts for the
stubbornness with which they cling to materialism—and for the hostility
that greets an intellectual who starts to wander off from the herd.
Materialism must be true because it “liberates us from religion.” The
positive mission Nagel undertakes in Mind and Cosmos is to
outline, cautiously, a possible Third Way between theism and
materialism, given that the first is unacceptable—emotionally, if not
intellectually—and the second is untenable. Perhaps matter itself has a
bias toward producing conscious creatures. Nature in that case would be
“teleological”—not random, not fully subject to chance, but tending
toward a particular end. Our mental life would be accounted
for—phew!—without reference to God.
I don’t think Nagel succeeds in finding his Third Way, and
I doubt he or his successors ever will, but then I have biases of my
own. There’s no doubting the honesty and intellectual courage—the free
thinking and ennobling good faith—that shine through his attempt.
Andrew Ferguson is a senior editor at The Weekly Standard.
No comments:
Post a Comment